Jump to content
IGNORED

Pentagon developing humanoid Terminator robots


Guest yikes

Recommended Posts

Guest yikes

fun for everyone!

 

http://www.naturalnews.com/039829_humanoid_robots_Pentagon_Terminator.html



(NaturalNews) Watch the video embedded below: It reveals the "Petman" humanoid robot funded by the Department of Defense. Like something ripped right out of a sci-fi movie, the robot sweats to regulate body temperature, and it can be dressed in chemical suits, camo or other uniforms to resemble humans. The picture you see at the top of this article is take from the actual humanoid robot currently under development.

Have no illusions about where this is headed: The Pentagon wants to develop and deploy a robotic army of autonomous soldiers that will kill without hesitation. It's only a matter of time before these robots are armed with rifles, grenade launchers and more. Their target acquisition systems can be a hybrid combination of both thermal and night vision technologies, allowing them to see humans at night and even detect heat signatures through building walls.

This is the army humanity is eventually going to face. You'd all better start getting familiar with theanatomy of humanoid robots so that you know where to shoot them for maximum incapacitation effect. You'd also better start learning how to sew thermal blankets into clothing, hoodies and scarves in order to fool thermal imaging systems.

At first, these robots will be deployed as soldier assistants, carrying gear, retrieving wounded soldiers from hot zones, and so on. But over time, the roles will be reversed: Robotic soldiers will serve on the front lines while humans only serve support roles to keep the robots running. Such a transition will take decades, of course, but it's coming.



What happens when the robots become self-aware?

A more apocalyptic scenario unfolds when the machines are taught to build self-replicating factories that one day gain enough intelligence to decide that humans are no longer needed. This is the scenario described in the movie "Terminator," where Skynet launches nuclear missiles in an attempt to destroy humanity.

Not coincidentally, an emerging technology of "cooperative drones" that allows small aircraft to carry heavy objects in flight is also being called "Skynet." Watch that creepy video below, narrated by Paul Joseph Watson of Infowars.com.

You need to be aware that all this is happening right now. The Pentagon is funding autonomous robots that fly, swim and walk. In very short order, weapons will be mounted to these drones, and the Pentagon will be in command of a sci-fi robotic army of drones. Remember the Clone Wars from Star Wars? You're about to see the "Drone Wars" for real.

Link to comment
Share on other sites

  • Replies 123
  • Created
  • Last Reply

Nice source bro. Clearly a well thought out piece by a man who knows what he's talking about, and didn't just watch Terminator the other day and get the idea to write about a Boston Dynamics youtube clip.

Link to comment
Share on other sites

ignore those trolls yikes and please post some links about the autonomy of those upcoming androids and maybe some instructional videos on how to counter them effectively.

 

thanks in advance.

Link to comment
Share on other sites

I just sent my students a link to a different article on the same topic (from Wired: http://www.wired.com/dangerroom/2013/04/petman-dressed/). (I'm currently teaching a class that's relevant to this topic.) It's pretty clear that these are not being designed to "kill you". On the contrary, the goal seems to make these into rescue bots for situations that are too dangerous for human rescue operations.

 

 

As much fun as the science fiction can be, it's probably best to be level-headed about this and avoid jumping off into futurist speculation la-la land. There are plenty of other moral considerations that this technology certainly raises, but when you start talking about Terminator-style worries, it's pretty easy to lose sight of the real issues, which might be more subtle but still very serious and worth our careful reflection.

Link to comment
Share on other sites

Guest yikes

http://mashable.com/2013/03/01/bigdog-robot-throws-cinder-blocks/



Robots are everywhere. In our cars, our factories and our homes. They're also running up the sides of steep hills and completely mastering tough terrain. At least that was BigDog's signature move — until now. The Boston Dynamicsrobot finally has an arm and it's using it to toss cinder blocks clear across the room.


Placed where the "dog's" head might normally be, the articulated appendage is being used right now to demonstrate how the robot can use its whole body to throw heavy objects, rather like a champion shot putter might throw a 10-pound ball 75 feet across a field.


BigDog is actually a Defense Advanced Research Projects Agency (DARPA) project, and the long-term goal is to create a robot that moves as well as a human or animal across difficult terrain.


About the size of a small mule or very big dog, BigDog weighs 240 pounds and uses a host of servos and sensors to dance its way across the ground at up to 4 miles per hour. It can carry loads of up to 340 pounds and will trundle on for nearly 13 miles before needing to refuel.


With its four animal-like legs, tiny feet and rather large body, it's quite impressive to watch, but BigDog's latest stunt is a combination of stunning and scary.


We'd guess that the autonomous BigDog coming at you might give you a start, but once it starts throwing things, well, then it wins. End of story. If you think we're being Nervous Nellies, listen closely to the video and you'll hear someone yelling a cautionary "throwing!" moments before each BigDog cinder block toss.


What do you think of Big Dog's newest capability and are you ready for autonomous and agile robots among us?


Check out some of our other favorite robots in the slideshow below.

Link to comment
Share on other sites

Guest yikes

keep laughing assholes..........

people in 3rd world countries [including women and children] are being wasted daily by drones without any trial or direct human interaction.

if you think robot tech is not going to be used by the pentagon on the battlefield or in controlling domestic "terrorists" or "civil unrest" in the next 1-20 years your head is most certainly up your ass.

 

http://www.nbcnews.com/technology/futureoftech/pentagon-wants-robot-surrogates-soldiers-157750

 

 

In yet another sign that science fiction and reality are on a collision course, the military's futuristic research arm wants to invest $7 million in a project to create robotic partners for its soldiers, according to DARPA's $2.8 billion budget for 2013.

DARPA watchers see an immediate link to, and inspiration from, the blockbuster movie "Avatar," in which humans plugged into a brain interface to control genetically enhanced human-alien hybrids.

The goal of the so-called "Avatar Project," reports Wired's Danger Room, is to "develop interfaces and algorithms to enable a soldier to effectively partner with a semi-autonomous bi-pedal machine and allow it to act as the solder's surrogate."

Speculation over what the military is actually after in the program is teed off from other robotic research programs funded by DARPA.

IEEE's Automation blog finds clues in the agency's work with Boston Dynamic's Petman, a bi-pedal robot designed to test chemical-protection clothing, which could serve as the surrogate.

"We have absolutely no evidence to suggest Petman is anything more than a chemical-protection clothing tester," IEEE's Evan Ackerman writes, "except for the fact that just testing suits seems like a slightly ridiculous use for a freakin' super advanced bipedal humanoid soldier robot."

Another possibility raised by Wired's Danger Room is the Alphadog, also built by Boston Dynamics.

Earlier this month, DARPA released a video of the robodog, which is capable of hauling a soldier's gear and following the soldier using "eyes" — sensors that can distinguish between trees, rocks, terrain obstacles and people.

"It sounds like the agency's after an even more sophisticated robot-soldier synergy," Wired notes, pointing to earlier research on mind-controlled robots.

"Granted, that research was performed on monkeys. But it does raise the tantalizing prospect that soldiers might one day meld minds with their very own robotic alter egos."

Link to comment
Share on other sites

Guest yikes

http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Military_robot

 

 

Examples [edit]In current use

220px-SWORDS.jpg
magnify-clip.png
Foster-Miller TALON SWORDS units equipped with various weaponry.

[edit]In development

220px-FCS-MULE-ARV-2007.jpg
magnify-clip.png
The Armed Robotic Vehicle variant of theMULE. Photo courtesy of U.S. Army.
  • US Mechatronics has produced a working automated sentry gun and is currently developing it further for commercial and military use.
  • MIDARS, a four-wheeled robot outfitted with several cameras, radar, and possibly a firearm, that automatically performs random or preprogrammed patrols around a military base or other government installation. It alerts a human overseer when it detects movement in unauthorized areas, or other programmed conditions. The operator can then instruct the robot to ignore the event, or take over remote control to deal with an intruder, or to get better camera views of an emergency. The robot would also regularly scan radio frequency identification tags (RFID) placed on stored inventory as it passed and report any missing items.
  • Tactical Autonomous Combatant (TAC) units, described in Project Alpha study'Unmanned Effects: Taking the Human out of the Loop' -
  • Autonomous Rotorcraft Sniper System is an experimental robotic weapons system being developed by the U.S. Army since 2005.[7][8] It consists of a remotely operated sniper rifle attached to an unmanned autonomous helicopter.[9] It is intended for use in urban combat or for several other missions requiring snipers.[10] Flight tests are scheduled to begin in Summer 2009.[7]
  • The "Mobile Autonomous Robot Software" research program was started in December 2003 by the Pentagon who purchased 15 Segways in an attempt to develop more advanced military robots.[11] The program was part of a $26 million Pentagon program to develop software for autonomous systems.[11]


"are we sure that yikes isn't just a Troon dupe?'

glad i'm friends w/troon and not you dickface

Link to comment
Share on other sites

Guest yikes

this issue is so big most of you can't really comprehend it.

 

and you are proud to boast of your stupidity and blissful ignorance,

 

http://www.hoover.org/publications/policy-review/article/135336

 

lethal sentry robot designed for perimeter protection, able to detect shapes and motions, and combined with computational technologies to analyze and differentiate enemy threats from friendly or innocuous objects — and shoot at the hostiles. A drone aircraft, not only unmanned but programmed to independently rove and hunt prey, perhaps even tracking enemy fighters who have been previously “painted and marked” by military forces on the ground. Robots individually too small and mobile to be easily stopped, but capable of swarming and assembling themselves at the final moment of attack into a much larger weapon. These (and many more) are among the ripening fruits of automation in weapons design. Some are here or close at hand, such as the lethal sentry robot designed in South Korea. Others lie ahead in a future less and less distant.

Lethal autonomous machines will inevitably enter the future battlefield — but they will do so incrementally, one small step at a time. The combination of “inevitable” and “incremental” development raises not only complex strategic and operational questions but also profound legal and ethical ones. Inevitability comes from both supply-side and demand-side factors. Advances in sensor and computational technologies will supply “smarter” machines that can be programmed to kill or destroy, while the increasing tempo of military operations and political pressures to protect one’s own personnel and civilian persons and property will demand continuing research, development, and deployment. The process will be incremental because nonlethal robotic systems (already proliferating on the battlefield, after all) can be fitted in their successive generations with both self-defensive and offensive technologies. As lethal systems are initially deployed, they may include humans in the decision-making loop, at least as a fail-safe — but as both the decision-making power of machines and the tempo of operations potentially increase, that human role will likely slowly diminish.

Recognizing the inevitable but incremental evolution of these technologies is key to addressing the legal and ethical dilemmas associated with them; U.S. policy for resolving such dilemmas should be built upon these assumptions. The certain yet gradual development and deployment of these systems, as well as the humanitarian advantages created by the precision of some systems, make some proposed responses — such as prohibitory treaties — unworkable as well as ethically questionable.

Those same features also make it imperative, though, that the United States resist its own impulses toward secrecy and reticence with respect to military technologies and recognize that the interests those tendencies serve are counterbalanced here by interests in shaping the normative terrain — i.e., the contours of international law as well as international expectations about appropriate conduct on which the United States government and others will operate militarily as technology evolves. Just as development of autonomous weapon systems will be incremental, so too will development of norms about acceptable systems and uses be incremental. The United States must act, however, before international expectations about these technologies harden around the views of those who would impose unrealistic, ineffective, or dangerous prohibitions — or those who would prefer few or no constraints at all.

INCREMENTAL AUTOMATION OF DRONES

The incremental march toward automated lethal technologies of the future, and the legal and ethical challenges that accompany it, can be illustrated by looking at today’s drone aircraft. Unmanned drones piloted from afar are already a significant component of the United States’ arsenal. At this writing, close to one in three U.S. Air Force aircraft is remotely piloted (though this number also includes many tiny tactical surveillance drones). The drone proportion will only grow. Yet current drone military aircraft are not autonomous in the firing of weapons — the weapon must be fired in real time by a human controller. So far there are no known plans or, apparently in the view of military, reasons to take the human out of the weapon firing loop.

Nor are today’s drones truly autonomous as aircraft. They require human pilots and flight support personnel in real time, even when they are located far away. They are, however, increasingly automated in their flight functions: self-landing capabilities, for example, and particularly automation to the point that a single controller can run many drone aircraft at once, increasing efficiency considerably. The automation of flight is gradually increasing as sensors and aircraft control through computer programming improves.

Some believe that the next generations of jet fighters won’t be manned. Or that manned fighters will join with unmanned.

Looking to the future, some observers believe that one of the next generations of jet fighter aircraft will no longer be manned, or at least that manned fighter aircraft will be joined by unmanned aircraft. Drone aircraft might gradually become capable of higher speeds, torques, g-forces, and other stresses than those a human pilot can endure (and perhaps at a cheaper cost as well). Given that speed in every sense — including turning and twisting in flight, reaction and decision times — is an advantage, design will emphasize automating as many of these functions as possible, in competition with the enemy’s systems.

Just as the aircraft might have to be maneuvered far too quickly for detailed human control of its movements, so too the weapons — against other aircraft, drones, or anti-aircraft systems — might have to be utilized at the same speeds in order to match the beyond-human speed of the aircraft’s own systems (as well as the enemy aircraft’s similarly automated counter-systems). In similar ways, defense systems on modern U.S. naval vessels have long been able to target incoming missiles automatically, with humans monitoring the system’s operation, because human decision-making processes are too slow to deal with multiple, inbound, high-speed missiles. Some military operators regard many emerging automated weapons systems as merely a more sophisticated form of “fire and forget” self-guided missiles. And because contemporary fighter aircraft are designed not only for air-to-air combat, but for ground attack missions as well, design changes that reduce the role of the human controller of the aircraft platform may shade into automation of the weapons directed at ground targets, too.

Although current remotely-piloted drones, on the one hand, and future autonomous weapons, on the other, are based on different technologies and operational imperatives, they generate some overlapping concerns about their ethical legitimacy and lawfulness. Today’s arguments over the legality of remotely-piloted, unmanned aircraft in their various missions (especially targeted killing operations, and concerns that the United States is using technology to shift risk from its own personnel onto remote-area civilian populations) presage the arguments that already loom over weapons systems that exhibit emerging features of autonomy. Those arguments also offer lessons to guide short- and long-term U.S. policy toward autonomous weapons generally, including systems that are otherwise quite different.

AUTOMATED-ARMS RACING?

These issues are easiest to imagine in the airpower context. But in other battlefield contexts, too, the United States and other sophisticated military powers (and eventually unsophisticated powers and nonstate actors, as such technologies become commodified and offered for licit or illicit sale) will find increasingly automated lethal systems more and more attractive. Moreover, as artificial intelligence improves, weapons systems will evolve from robotic “automation” — the execution of precisely pre-programmed actions or sequences in a well-defined and controlled environment — toward genuine “autonomy,” meaning the robot is capable of generating actions to adapt to changing and unpredictable environments.

Take efforts to protect peacekeepers facing the threat of snipers or ambush in an urban environment: Small mobile robots with weapons could act as roving scouts for the human soldiers, with “intermediate” automation — the robot might be pre-programmed to look for certain enemy weapon signatures and to alert a human operator, who then decides whether or not to pull the trigger. In the next iteration, the system might be set with the human being not required to give an affirmative command, but instead merely deciding whether to override and veto a machine-initiated attack. That human decision-maker also might not be a soldier on site, but an off-battlefield, remote robot-controller.

It will soon become clear that the communications link between human and weapon system could be jammed or hacked (and in addition, speed and the complications of the pursuit algorithms may seem better left to the machine itself, especially once the technology moves to many small, swarming, lightly armed robots). One technological response will be to reduce the vulnerability of the communications link by severing it, thus making the robot dependent upon executing its own programming, or even genuinely autonomous.

Aside from conventional war on conventional battlefields, covert or special operations will involve their own evolution toward incrementally autonomous systems. Consider intelligence gathering in the months preceding the raid on Osama bin Laden’s compound. Tiny surveillance robots equipped with facial recognition technology might have helped affirmatively identify bin Laden much earlier. It is not a large step to weaponize such systems and then perhaps go the next step to allow them to act autonomously, perhaps initially with a human remote-observer as a fail-safe, but with very little time to override programmed commands.

These examples have all been stylized to sound precise and carefully controlled. At some point in the near future, however, someone — China, Russia, or someone else — will likely design, build, and deploy (or sell) an autonomous weapon system for battlefield use that is programmed to target something — say a person or position — that is firing a weapon and is positively identified as hostile rather than friendly. A weapon system programmed, that is, to do one thing: identify the locus of enemy fire and fire back. It thus would lack the ability altogether to take account of civilian presence and any likely collateral damage.

Quite apart from the security and war-fighting implications, the U.S. government would have grave legal and humanitarian concerns about such a foreign system offered for sale on the international arms markets, let alone deployed and used. Yet the United States would then find itself in a peculiar situation — potentially facing a weapon system on the battlefield that conveys significant advantages to its user, but which the United States would not deploy itself because (for reasons described below) it does not believe it is a legal weapon. The United States will have to come up with technological counters and defenses such as development of smaller, more mobile, armed robots able to “hide” as well as “hunt” on their own.

The implication is that the arms race in battlefield robots will be more than simply a race for ever more autonomous weapons systems. More likely, it will mostly be a race for ways to counter and defend against them — partly through technical means, but also partly through the tools of international norms and diplomacy, provided, however, that those norms are not over-invested with hopes that cannot realistically be met.

LEGAL AND ETHICAL REQUIREMENTS

The legal and ethical evaluation of a new weapons system is nothing new. It is a long-standing requirement of the laws of war, one taken seriously by U.S. military lawyers. In recent years, U.S. military judge advocates have rejected proposed new weapons as incompatible with the laws of war, including blinding laser weapons and, reportedly, various cutting edge cyber-technologies that might constitute weapons for purposes of the laws of war. But arguments over the legitimacy of particular weapons (or their legitimate use) go back to the beginnings of debate over the laws and ethics of war: the legitimacy, for example, of poison, the crossbow, submarines, aerial bombardment, antipersonnel landmines, chemical and biological weapons, and nuclear weapons. In that historical context, debate over autonomous robotic weapons — the conditions of their lawfulness as weapons and the conditions of their lawful use — is nothing novel.

Likewise, there is nothing novel in the sorts of responses autonomous weapons systems will generate. On the one hand, emergence of a new weapon often sparks an insistence in some quarters that the weapon is ethically and legally abhorrent and should be prohibited by law. On the other hand, the historical reality is that if a new weapon system greatly advantages a side, the tendency is for it gradually to be adopted by others perceiving they can benefit from it, too. In some cases, legal prohibitions on the weapon system as such erode, as happened with submarines and airplanes; what survives is typically legal rules for the use of the new weapon, with greater or lesser specificity. In a few cases (including some very important ones), legal prohibitions on the weapon as such gain hold. The ban on poison gas, for example, has survived in one form or another with very considerable effectiveness throughout the 20th century.

Where in the long history of new weapons and their ethical and legal regulation will autonomous robotic weapons fit?

Where in this long history of new weapons and their ethical and legal regulation will autonomous robotic weapons fit? What are the features of autonomous robotic weapons that raise ethical and legal concerns? How should they be addressed, as a matter of law and process? By treaty, for example, or by some other means?

One answer to these questions is: wait and see. It is too early to know where the technology will go, so the debate over ethical and legal principles for robotic autonomous weapons should be deferred until a system is at hand. Otherwise it is just an exercise in science fiction and fantasy.

But that wait-and-see view is shortsighted and mistaken. Not all the important innovations in autonomous weapons are so far off. Some are possible now or will be in the near term, and some of them raise serious questions of law and ethics even at their current research and development stage.

Moreover, looking to the long term, technology and weapons innovation does not take place in a vacuum. The time to take into account law and ethics to inform and govern autonomous weapons systems is now, before technologies and weapons development have become “hardened” in a particular path and their design architecture becomes difficult or even impossible to change. Otherwise, the risk is that technology and innovation alone, unleavened by ethics and law at the front end of the innovation process, let slip the robots of war.

This is also the time — before ethical and legal understandings of autonomous weapon systems likewise become hardened in the eyes of key constituents of the international system — to propose and defend a framework for evaluating them that advances simultaneously strategic and moral interests. What might such a framework look like? Consider the traditional legal and ethical paradigm to which autonomous weapons systems must conform, and then the major objections and responses being advanced today by critics of autonomous weapons.

A LEGAL AND ETHICAL FRAMEWORK

The baseline legal and ethical principles governing the introduction of any new weapon are distinction (or discrimination) and proportionality. Distinction says that for a weapon to be lawful, it must be capable of being aimed at lawful targets, in a way that discriminates between military targets and civilians and their objects. Although most law-of-war concerns about discrimination run to the use of a weapon — Is it being used with no serious care in aiming it? — in extreme cases, a weapon itself might be regarded as inherently indiscriminate. Any autonomous robot weapon system will have to possess the ability to be aimed, or aim itself, at an acceptable legal level of discrimination.

Proportionality adds that even if a weapon meets the test of distinction, any actual use of a weapon must also involve an evaluation that sets the anticipated military advantage to be gained against the anticipated civilian harm (to civilian persons or objects). The harm to civilians must not be excessive relative to the expected military gain. While easy to state in the abstract, this evaluation for taking into account civilian collateral damage is difficult for many reasons. While everyone agrees that civilian harm should not be excessive in relation to military advantages gained, the comparison is apples and oranges. Although there is a general sense that excess can be determined in truly gross cases, there is no accepted formula that gives determinate outcomes in specific cases; it is at bottom a judgment rather than a calculus. Nonetheless, it is a fundamental requirement of the law and ethics of war that any military operation undertake this judgment, and that must be true of any autonomous weapon system’s programming as well.

These are daunting legal and ethical hurdles if the aim is to create a true “robot soldier.” One way to think about the requirements of the “ethical robot soldier,” however, is to ask what we would require of an ethical human soldier performing the same function.

Some leading roboticists have been studying ways in which machine programming might eventually capture the two fundamental principles of distinction and proportionality. As for programming distinction, one could theoretically start with fixed lists of lawful targets — for example, programmed targets could include persons or weapons that are firing at the robot — and gradually build upwards toward inductive reasoning about characteristics of lawful targets not already on the list. Proportionality, for programming purposes, is a relative judgment: Measure anticipated civilian harm and measure military advantage; subtract and measure the balance against some determined standard of “excessive”; if excessive, do not attack an otherwise lawful target. Difficult as these calculations seem to any experienced law-of-war lawyer, they are nevertheless the fundamental conditions that the ethically-designed and -programmed robot soldier would have to satisfy and therefore what a programming development effort must take into account. The ethical and legal engineering matter every bit as much as the mechanical or software engineering.

FOUR OBJECTIONS

If this is the optimistic vision of the robot soldier of, say, decades from now, it is subject already to four main grounds of objection. The first is a general empirical skepticism that machine programming could ever reach the point of satisfying the fundamental ethical and legal principles of distinction and proportionality. Artificial intelligence has overpromised before. Once into the weeds of the judgments that these broad principles imply, the requisite intuition, cognition, and judgment look ever more marvelous — if not downright chimerical when attributed to a future machine.

This skepticism is essentially factual, a question of how technology evolves over decades. Noted, it is quite possible that fully autonomous weapons will never achieve the ability to meet these standards, even far into the future. Yet we do not want to rule out such possibilities — including the development of technologies of war that, by turning decision chains over to machines, might indeed reduce risks to civilians by making targeting more precise and firing decisions more controlled, especially compared to human soldiers whose failings might be exacerbated by fear, vengeance, or other emotions.

It is true that relying on the promise of computer analytics and artificial intelligence risks pushing us down a slippery slope, propelled by the promise of future technology to overcome human failings rather than addressing them directly. If forever unmet, it becomes magical thinking, not technological promise. Even so, articulation of the tests of lawfulness that autonomous systems must ultimately meet helps channel technological development toward the law of war’s protective ends.

A second objection is a categorical moral one which says that it is simply wrong per se to take the human moral agent entirely out of the firing loop. A machine, no matter how good, cannot completely replace the presence of a true moral agent in the form of a human being possessed of a conscience and the faculty of moral judgment (even if flawed in human ways). In that regard, the title of this essay is deliberately provocative in pairing “robot” and “soldier,” because, on this objection, such a pairing is precisely what should never be attempted.

This is a difficult argument to engage, since it stops with a moral principle that one either accepts or not. Moreover, it raises a further question as to what constitutes the tipping point into impermissible autonomy, given that the automation of weapons functions is likely to occur in incremental steps.

The third objection holds that autonomous weapons systems that remove the human being from the firing loop are unacceptable because they undermine the possibility of holding anyone accountable for what, if done by a human soldier, might be a war crime. If the decision to fire is made by a machine, who should be held responsible for mistakes? The soldier who allowed the weapon system to be used and make a bad decision? The commander who chose to employ it on the battlefield? The engineer or designer who programmed it in the first place?

One objection holds that autonomous weapons systems undermine the possibility of holding anyone accountable.

This is an objection particularly salient to those who put significant faith in laws-of-war accountability by mechanisms of individual criminal liability, whether through international tribunals or other judicial mechanisms. But post-hoc judicial accountability in war is just one of many mechanisms for promoting and enforcing compliance with the laws of war, and its global effectiveness is far from clear. Devotion to individual criminal liability as the presumptive mechanism of accountability risks blocking development of machine systems that would, if successful, reduce actual harm to civilians on or near the battlefield.

Finally, the long-run development of autonomous weapon systems faces the objection that, by removing one’s human soldiers from risk and reducing harm to civilians through greater precision, the disincentive to resort to armed force is diminished. The result might be a greater propensity to use military force and wage war.

As a moral matter, this objection is subject to a moral counter-objection. Why not just forgo all easily obtained protections for civilians or soldiers in war for fear that without holding these humans “hostage,” so to speak, political leaders would be tempted to resort to war more than they ought? Moreover, as an empirical matter, this objection is not so special to autonomous weapons. Precisely the same objection can be raised with respect to remotely-piloted drones — and, generally, with respect to any technological development that either reduces risk to one’s own forces or, especially perversely, reduces risk to civilians, because it invites more frequent recourse to force.

These four objections run to the whole enterprise of building the autonomous robot soldier, and important debates could be held around each of them. Whatever their merits in theory, however, they all face a practical difficulty: the incremental way autonomous weapon systems will develop. After all, these objections are often voiced as though there was likely to be some determinate, ascertainable point when the human-controlled system becomes the machine-controlled one. It seems far more likely, however, that the evolution of weapons technology will be gradual, slowly and indistinctly eroding the role of the human in the firing loop. And crucially, the role of real-time human decision-making will be phased out in some military contexts in order to address some technological or strategic issue unrelated to autonomy, such as the speed of the system’s response. “Incrementality” does not by itself render any of these universal objections wrong per se — but it does suggest that there is another kind of discussion to be had about regulation of weapons systems undergoing gradual, step-by-step change.

INTERNATIONAL TREATIES AND INCREMENTAL EVOLUTION

Critics sometimes portray the United States as engaged in relentless, heedless pursuit of technological advantage — whether in drones or other robotic weapons systems — that will inevitably be fleeting as other countries mimic, steal, or reverse engineer its technologies. According to this view, if the United States would quit pursuing these technologies, the genie might remain in the bottle or at least emerge much more slowly and in any case under greater restraint.

This is almost certainly wrong, in part because the technologies at issue — drone aircraft or driverless cars, for example — are going to spread with respect to general use far outside of military applications. They are already doing so faster than many observers of technology would have guessed. And the decision architectures that would govern firing a weapon are not so completely removed from those of, say, an elder-care robot engaged in home-assisted living programmed to decide when to take emergency action.

Moreover, even with respect to militarily-specific applications of autonomous robotics advances, critics worrying that the United States is spurring a new arms race overlook just how many military-technological advances result from U.S. efforts to find technological “fixes” to successive forms of violation of the basic laws of war committed by its adversaries. A challenge for the United States and its allies is that it is typically easier and faster for nonstate adversaries to come up with new behaviors that violate the laws of war to gain advantage than it is to come up with new technological counters.

In part because it is also easier and faster for states that are competitively engaged with the United States to deploy systems that are, in the U.S. view, ethically and legally deficient, the United States does have a strong interest in seeing that development and deployment of autonomous battlefield robots be regulated, legally and ethically. Moreover, critics are right to argue that even if U.S. abstention from this new arms race alone would not prevent the proliferation of new destructive technologies, it would nonetheless be reckless for the United States to pursue them without a strategy for responding to other states’ or actors’ use for military ends. That strategy necessarily includes a role for normative constraints.

These observations — and alarm at the apparent development of an arms race around these emerging and future weapons — lead many today to believe that an important part of the solution lies in some form of multilateral treaty. A proposed treaty might be “regulatory,” restricting acceptable weapons systems or regulating their acceptable use (in the manner, for example, that certain sections of the Chemical Weapons Convention or Biological Weapons Convention regulate the monitoring and reporting of dual use chemical or biological precursors). Alternatively, a treaty might be flatly “prohibitory”; some advocacy groups have already moved to the point of calling for international conventions that would essentially ban autonomous weapons systems altogether, along the lines of the Ottawa Convention banning antipersonnel landmines.

Ambitions for multilateral treaty regulation (of either kind) in this context are misguided for several reasons. To start with, limitations on autonomous military technologies, although quite likely to find wide superficial acceptance among nonfighting states and some nongovernmental groups and actors, will have little traction with states whose practice matters most, whether they admit to this or not. Israel might well be the first state to deploy a genuinely autonomous weapon system, but for strategic reasons not reveal it until actually used in battle. Some states, particularly Asian allies worried about a rising and militarily assertive China, may want the United States to be more aggressive, not less, in adopting the latest technologies, given that their future adversary is likely to have fewer scruples about the legality or ethics of its own autonomous weapon systems. America’s key Asian allies might well favor nearly any technological development that extends the reach and impact of U.S. forces or enhances their own ability to counter adversary capabilities.

Even states and groups inclined to support treaty prohibitions or limitations will find it difficult to reach agreement on scope or workable definitions because lethal autonomy will be introduced incrementally. As battlefield machines become smarter and faster, and the real-time human role in controlling them gradually recedes, agreeing on what constitutes a prohibited autonomous weapon will likely be unattainable. Moreover, no one should forget that there are serious humanitarian risks to prohibition, given the possibility that autonomous weapons systems could in the long run be more discriminating and ethically preferable to alternatives. Blanket prohibition precludes the possibility of such benefits. And, of course, there are the endemic challenges of compliance — the collective action problems of failure and defection that afflict all such treaty regimes.

PRINCIPLES, POLICIES, AND PROCESSES

Nevertheless, the dangers associated with evolving autonomous robotic weapons are very real, and the United States has a serious interest in guiding development in this context of international norms. By international norms we do not mean new binding legal rules only — whether treaty rules or customary international law — but instead widely-held expectations about legally or ethically appropriate conduct, whether formally binding or not. Among the reasons the United States should care is that such norms are important for guiding and constraining its internal practices, such as r&d and eventual deployment of autonomous lethal systems it regards as legal. They help earn and sustain necessary buy-in from the officers and lawyers who would actually use or authorize such systems in the field. They assist in establishing common standards among the United States and its partners and allies to promote cooperation and permit joint operations. And they raise the political and diplomatic costs to adversaries of developing, selling, or using autonomous lethal systems that run afoul of these standards.

A better approach than treaties is the gradual development of internal state norms and best practices.

A better approach than treaties for addressing these systems is the gradual development of internal state norms and best practices. Worked out incrementally, debated, and applied to the weapons development processes of the United States, they can be carried outwards to discussions with others around the world. This requires long-term, sustained effort combining internal ethical and legal scrutiny — including specific principles, policies, and processes — and external diplomacy.

To be successful, the United States government would have to resist two extreme instincts. It would have to resist its own instincts to hunker down behind secrecy and avoid discussing and defending even guiding principles. It would also have to refuse to cede the moral high ground to critics of autonomous lethal systems, opponents demanding some grand international treaty or multilateral regime to regulate or even prohibit them.

The United States government should instead carefully and continuously develop internal norms, principles, and practices that it believes are correct for the design and implementation of such systems. It should also prepare to articulate clearly to the world the fundamental legal and moral principles by which all parties ought to judge autonomous weapons, whether those of the United States or those of others.

The core, baseline principles can and should be drawn and adapted from the customary law-of-war framework: distinction and proportionality. A system must be capable of being aimed at lawful targets — distinction — but how good must that capability be in any particular circumstance? The legal threshold has historically depended in part upon the general state of aiming technology, as well as the intended use. Proportionality, for its part, requires that any use of a weapon must take into account collateral harm to civilians. This rules out systems that simply identify and aim at other weapons without taking civilians into account — but once again, what is the standard of care for an autonomous lethal system in any particular “proportionality” circumstance? This is partly a technical issue of designing systems capable of discerning and estimating civilian harm, but also partly an ethical issue of attaching weights to the variables at stake.

The U.S. must develop a set of principles to regulate and govern advanced autonomous weapons.

These questions move from overarching ethical and legal principles to processes that make sure these principles are concretely taken into account — not just down the road at the deployment stage but much earlier, during ther&d stage. It will not work to go forward with design and only afterwards, seeing the technology, to decide what changes need to be made in order to make the system’s decision-making conform to legal requirements. By then it may be too late. Engineering designs will have been set for both hardware and software; significant national investment into r&d already undertaken that will be hard to write off on ethical or legal grounds; and national prestige might be in play. This would be true of the United States but also other states developing such systems. Legal review by that stage would tend to be one of justification at the back end, rather than seeking best practices at the front end.

The United States must develop a set of principles to regulate and govern advanced autonomous weapons not just to guide its own systems, but also to effectively assess the systems of other states. This requires that the United States work to bring along its partners and allies — including nato members and technologically advanced Asian allies — by developing common understandings of norms and best practices as the technology evolves in often small steps. Just as development of autonomous weapon systems will be incremental, so too will development of norms about acceptable systems and uses.

Internal processes should therefore be combined with public articulation of overarching policies. Various vehicles for declaring policy might be utilized over time — perhaps directives by the secretary of defense — followed by periodic statements explaining the legal rationale behind decisions about r&d and deployment of weapon technologies. The United States has taken a similar approach in the recent past to other controversial technologies, most notably cluster munitions and landmines, by declaring commitment to specific standards that balance operational necessities with humanitarian imperatives.

To be sure, this proposal risks papering over enormous practical and policy difficulties. The natural tendency of the U.S. national security community — likewise that of other major state powers — will be to discuss little or nothing, for fear of revealing capabilities or programming to adversaries, as well as inviting industrial espionage and reverse engineering of systems. Policy statements will necessarily be more general and less factually specific than critics would like. Furthermore, one might reasonably question not only whether broad principles such as distinction and proportionality can be machine-coded at all but also whether they can be meaningfully discussed publicly if the relevant facts might well be distinguishable only in terms of digital ones and zeroes buried deep in computer code.

These concerns are real, but there are at least two mitigating solutions. First, as noted, the United States will need to resist its own impulses toward secrecy and reticence with respect to military technologies, recognizing that the interests those tendencies serve are counterbalanced here by interests in shaping the normative terrain on which it and others will operate militarily as technology quickly evolves. The legitimacy of such inevitably controversial systems in the public and international view matters too. It is better that the United States work to set global standards than let other states or groups set them.

Of course, there are limits to transparency here, on account of both secrecy concerns and the practical limits of persuading skeptical audiences about the internal and undisclosed decision-making capacities of rapidly evolving robotic systems. A second part of the solution is therefore to emphasize the internal processes by which the United States considers, develops, and tests its weapon systems. Legal review of any new weapon system is required as a matter of international law; the U.S. military would conduct it in any event. Even when the United States cannot disclose publicly the details of its automated systems and their internal programming, however, it should be quite open about its vetting procedures, both at the r&d stage and at the deployment stage, including the standards and metrics it uses.

Although the United States cannot be too public about the results of such tests, it should be prepared to share them with its close military allies as part of an effort to establish common standards. Looking more speculatively ahead, the standards the United States applies internally in developing its systems might eventually form the basis of export control standards. As other countries develop their own autonomous lethal systems, the United States can lead in forging a common export control regime and standards of acceptable autonomous weapons available on international markets.

A TRADITIONAL APPROACH TO A NEW CHALLENGE

In the end, one might still raise an entirely different objection altogether to these proposals: That the United States should not unnecessarily constrain itself in advance through a set of normative commitments, given vast uncertainties about the technology and future security environment. Better cautiously to wait, the argument might go, and avoid binding itself to one or another legal or ethical interpretation until it needs to. This fails to appreciate, however, that while significant deployment of highly-autonomous systems may be far off, r&d decisions are already upon us. Moreover, shaping international norms is a long-term process, and unless the United States and its allies accept some risk in starting it now, they may lose the opportunity to do so later.

In the end, all of this is a rather traditional approach — relying on the gradual evolution and adaptation of long-standing law-of-war principles. The challenges are scarcely novel.

Some view these automated technology developments as a crisis for the laws of war. But provided we start now to incorporate ethical and legal norms into weapons design, the incremental movement from automation to genuine machine autonomy already underway might well be made to serve the ends of law on the battlefield.

Link to comment
Share on other sites

Guest yikes

yep, yikes is definitely a troon dupe.

 

CONFIRMED

you are a brain dead moron/sheeple

CONFIRMED

 

btw

how does the lawn taste?

Link to comment
Share on other sites

Yeah, the government is using drones and that's scary. But bad journalism is bad journalism; the article you linked initially was grossly misleading and that's why I came at it with sarcasm... Basically, 1. PETMAN is not designed to kill, it's designed to test hazmat suits. That's all it's good at. Check out Boston Dynamic's page about it if you need details, but please don't take your information from fear mongering journalists, that doesn't help anyone. 2. The Natural News article, written by a nutritionist (...why am I listening to a nutritionist discuss speculative robotic advances again?), suggests that PETMAN is going to be used to kill human beings, and that it is going to become self aware in its factories and consider human life expendable. This is the same amount of logic currently being deployed in the "help this girl get her surgery thread" where some members have assumed this girl is going to get a transgender operation because she looks manly. That is to say, no logic has been deployed whatsoever.

 

Please consider your sources carefully dude, the last thread/article you posted was some scam about footless chickens in KFC, which had already been debunked a number of times on various sites...

Link to comment
Share on other sites

Guest yikes

http://www.nytimes.com/2005/02/16/technology/16robots.html?_r=0

 

The American military is working on a new generation of soldiers, far different from the army it has.

"They don't get hungry," said Gordon Johnson of the Joint Forces Command at the Pentagon. "They're not afraid. They don't forget their orders. They don't care if the guy next to them has just been shot. Will they do a better job than humans? Yes."

The robot soldier is coming.

The Pentagon predicts that robots will be a major fighting force in the American military in less than a decade, hunting and killing enemies in combat. Robots are a crucial part of the Army's effort to rebuild itself as a 21st-century fighting force, and a $127 billion project called Future Combat Systems is the biggest military contract in American history.

The military plans to invest tens of billions of dollars in automated armed forces. The costs of that transformation will help drive the Defense Department's budget up almost 20 percent, from a requested $419.3 billion for next year to $502.3 billion in 2010, excluding the costs of war. The annual costs of buying new weapons is scheduled to rise 52 percent, from $78 billion to $118.6 billion.

Military planners say robot soldiers will think, see and react increasingly like humans. In the beginning, they will be remote-controlled, looking and acting like lethal toy trucks. As the technology develops, they may take many shapes. And as their intelligence grows, so will their autonomy.

The robot soldier has been a dream at the Pentagon for 30 years. And some involved in the work say it may take at least 30 more years to realize in full. Well before then, they say, the military will have to answer tough questions if it intends to trust robots with the responsibility of distinguishing friend from foe, combatant from bystander.

Even the strongest advocates of automatons say war will always be a human endeavor, with death and disaster. And supporters like Robert Finkelstein, president of Robotic Technology in Potomac, Md., are telling the Pentagon it could take until 2035 to develop a robot that looks, thinks and fights like a soldier. The Pentagon's "goal is there," he said, "but the path is not totally clear."

Robots in battle, as envisioned by their builders, may look and move like humans or hummingbirds, tractors or tanks, cockroaches or crickets. With the development of nanotechnology - the science of very small structures - they may become swarms of "smart dust." The Pentagon intends for robots to haul munitions, gather intelligence, search buildings or blow them up.

All these are in the works, but not yet in battle. Already, however, several hundred robots are digging up roadside bombs in Iraq, scouring caves in Afghanistan and serving as armed sentries at weapons depots.

By April, an armed version of the bomb-disposal robot will be in Baghdad, capable of firing 1,000 rounds a minute. Though controlled by a soldier with a laptop, the robot will be the first thinking machine of its kind to take up a front-line infantry position, ready to kill enemies.

"The real world is not Hollywood," said Rodney A. Brooks, director of the Computer Science and Artificial Intelligence Laboratory at M.I.T. and a co-founder of the iRobot Corporation. "Right now we have the first few robots that are actually useful to the military."

Despite the obstacles, Congress ordered in 2000 that a third of the ground vehicles and a third of deep-strike aircraft in the military must become robotic within a decade. If that mandate is to be met, the United States will spend many billions of dollars on military robots by 2010.

As the first lethal robots head for Iraq, the role of the robot soldier as a killing machine has barely been debated. The history of warfare suggests that every new technological leap - the longbow, the tank, the atomic bomb - outraces the strategy and doctrine to control it.

"The lawyers tell me there are no prohibitions against robots making life-or-death decisions," said Mr. Johnson, who leads robotics efforts at the Joint Forces Command research center in Suffolk, Va. "I have been asked what happens if the robot destroys a school bus rather than a tank parked nearby. We will not entrust a robot with that decision until we are confident they can make it."

Trusting robots with potentially lethal decision-making may require a leap of faith in technology not everyone is ready to make. Bill Joy, a co-founder of Sun Microsystems, has worried aloud that 21st-century robotics and nanotechnology may become "so powerful that they can spawn whole new classes of accidents and abuses."

Link to comment
Share on other sites

Guest yikes

i'm throwing some stuff out there for speculation and discussion.

you might not agree on the sources or the content but that doesn't mean its not worth discussing given the tech-centric nature of the forum.

kinda glad it offends people and sort of alerts us to who the unenlightened sheeple are on the board.

the knee jerk reaction of 'HES A TROLL HES TROON" is laughably pathetic.

run and tell mommy

Link to comment
Share on other sites

 

yep, yikes is definitely a troon dupe.

 

CONFIRMED

you are a brain dead moron/sheeple

CONFIRMED

 

btw

how does the lawn taste?

rich, coming from the person who believes what he reads on those articles.

Link to comment
Share on other sites

i work in a lab that does human-robot interaction research for the government.

 

we are really, really far away from this. shit, we still haven't mastered computer vision and you expect autonomous intelligent machines? deal with reality, dude.

 

that isn't to say that work isn't going into developing autonomous robots that could be used for military applications. but you are seriously underestimating the complexity of human cognition if you think we're gonna have terminators and shit in the next couple of decades. the robots we're developing now will be spotters and pack mules. i don't see AIs being developed within the next half century, maybe more. i do think we're going to begin augmenting our own bodies with technology. why build the tech from the ground up when you can just stick a meat brain inside a metal shell (ok, not that simple obviously, but the point stands).



i'm throwing some stuff out there for speculation and discussion.

you might not agree on the sources or the content but that doesn't mean its not worth discussing given the tech-centric nature of the forum.

kinda glad it offends people and sort of alerts us to who the unenlightened sheeple are on the board.

the knee jerk reaction of 'HES A TROLL HES TROON" is laughably pathetic.

run and tell mommy

 

your hostility is annoying.

Link to comment
Share on other sites

Guest yikes

"1. PETMAN is not designed to kill, it's designed to test hazmat suits. "

 

if you think they won't weaponize ANY of the tech and use it for war you are surely living with your head in the sand.

Link to comment
Share on other sites

Guest yikes

as if death by drone isn't scary enough

there was a day not that long ago when this was unimaginable.

the idea of a military humanoid robot killing machine is not a matter or how but when.

Link to comment
Share on other sites

Archived

This topic is now archived and is closed to further replies.

  • Recently Browsing   0 members

    • No registered users viewing this page.
×
×
  • Create New...

Important Information

We have placed cookies on your device to help make this website better. You can adjust your cookie settings, otherwise we'll assume you're okay to continue.